Sunday, January 15, 2017

Aristotle - Definition of Tragedy

Aristotle’s Definition of Tragedy
                          “The living spirit hidden in a philosophy can only be brought to light by a kindered spirit”
is the dictum of Hegel. It is true in the case of Aristotle. For the first time in the history of literary criticism, it was Aristotle who gave serious thoughts to the theory of tragedy and enunciated a theory which remains important even today on account of its inherent elasticity and comprehensiveness. Aristotle’s Poetics is a short treatise in twenty six chapters neither exhaustive and comprehensive nor yet a coherent treatment of the subject with which it deals. Poetics is chiefly concerned with tragedy, which is regarded as the highest form of literature. But Abercrombie says,
“The theory of tragedy is worked out with such an insight and comprehension, that it becomes the type of the theory of literature.”
            Aristotle had at his disposal the works of the great tragic poets of the fifth century B.C. He studied this material deeply and tried to arrive at general principles with the aid of his philosophical thoughts. There could be no better example of Aristotle’s useful power of provoking disagreement than his definition of tragedy. He writes,
 “Tragedy is an imitation of an action which is serious, complete, and of a certain magnitude; in language embellished with each kind of artistic ornaments, the several kinds being found in the separate parts of the play; in form of action not of narrative; through pity and fear effecting the proper purgation of these emotions.” 
Aristotle’s definition of tragedy has wide implication. It naturally falls into two divisions. The first three clauses deal with the nature of tragedy and the second part describes the function or the emotional effect of tragedy. This can be explained in the following manner.
        


From the above definition, we find that Aristotle has recognized six significant parts of tragedy:
1.      Action or Ploy (Muthos)
2.      Character (Eithos)
3.      Thought (Dianoia)
4.      Diction (Lexis)
5.      Melody (Melos)
6.      Spectacle (Opsis)

The nature of tragedy is defined by that what is imitated i.e. action, thought and character are the objects of imitation, by that which the imitation occurs i.e. diction and melody and by the way how the imitation occurs i.e. spectacle is the manner of imitation. To begin with Aristotle’s statement that ‘tragedy is an imitation of an action’, tragedy is here considered as one of the imitative arts. What the tragedy imitates is an action or men in action. By action, Aristotle suggests a chain of events or an arrangement of incidents. Action does not mean mere outward physical movement, but also the inward working of mind and soul.

The action a tragedy imitates, must be ‘serious, complete in itself and of a certain magnitude.’ By the term ‘serious’ he denotes that tragic action should not be trivial, there must be grandeur and sublimity in action. ‘The action should be complete in itself’ implies that it must have a beginning, a middle and an end. The beginning is that from which further action flows out and which is intelligible in itself and not consequent or dependent on any previous situation. A middle is that which follows inevitably upon what has gone before and also leads on to an inevitable conclusion.  A satisfying end is that which follows inevitably from what has gone before but which does not lead to further action. ‘It must be of certain magnitude’ implies the sense of size and length. The action should be of moderate length i.e. neither too short nor too long. Lastly by ‘language embellished with each kind of artistic ornament’ Aristotle refers to the medium of an imitation. By various embellishments in various parts, Aristotle means verse in the dialogue and song. Tragedy imitates through verse in dialogue and through song in the Choric parts which are regarded as essential or indispensable for the success of a tragedy.

The second half of Aristotle’s definition of tragedy throws light on the function of tragedy. The function of tragedy, according to him, is ‘to bring out’, by means of emotions of pity and fear. He does not apply any explanation of the function of tragedy. Hence the critics have advanced a number of explanations and the term ‘Catharsis’ has been variously interpreted. Tragedy first excites the emotions of pity and fear and by excitement offers a pleasurable relief. Tragedy must combine the elements of pity and fear. Fear alone would make tragedy too gruesome or horrible whereas pity alone would make it too sentimental. Pity and fear are strictly co-related feeling. We should fear for ourselves. Pity, however, turns into fear where the object is so nearly related to us that the suffering of the hero seems to be our own.
David Daiches says,
“Tragedy gives new knowledge and produces a better state of mind. Tragedy imparts pleasure. It delights us by affording the shadow of that pleasure which excites in pain.”
Catharsis refers to the tragic varieties of pleasures. To provide such pleasure is the function of tragedy as well as the reason why men write, present and witness tragedies.
            
 Aristotle clearly tells us that we should not seek every pleasure from tragedy but ‘only the pleasure proper to it.’ The tragic pleasure is the pleasure of experience learning. There are many connotations of the experience, save the tragic pleasure which are neither covered under Aristotle’s doctrine of Catharsis nor can be expressed rationally by the same. Catharsis is pleasure only because it is a process of learning. The experience of tragedy is a king of insight experience and this experience is pleasurable and because it is a kind of learning. Watching tragedy enhances our understanding of life and leaves us face to face with the universal law. When in a tragedy we see a great hero reconciled to our little lots with the feeling of subconscious jealousy being satisfied:
            
“How are the mighty fallen!”















No comments:

Post a Comment

OLD ENGLISH PERIOD

  OLD ENGLISH PERIOD 1. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND Little is known of the history of the old English period and indeed very little is extant ...

Popular